DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY
THE UNIVERSITY OF HONG KONG
(Main Building, 3rd floor)
Philosophy of the Sciences, meetings 15, 16 & 17
Biology, Psychology and Social Science
lecturer: Professor F.C.T. Moore
 


Summary


The Human Sciences
 
    The disciplines which relate entirely or partly to (aspects of) human beings are very varied.  Here is an arbitrary list: archaeology, architecture, biology, cognitive science, ecology, education, economics, epidemiology, history, history of art, law, linguistics, literature, medicine, music, political science, psychology, sociology, textual criticism.  The list is arbitrary since it is incomplete, and takes no account of the (arguable) hierarchy of disciplines.  Medicine, linguistics, biology, for instance, all include many different sub-disciplines.
    So the question how the "human sciences" are related to each other deserves consideration.  If they all are concerned (at least in part) with the human species they cannot be unrelated to each other, can they ?  Here we ask how these relations have been and should be viewed.
    In eighteenth century Europe, many advocated a "science of man", hoping that it would be possible to achieve a human science which would provide a similar revolutionary simplification and systematization of our understanding of human beings, of ourselves, to that which they considered that Newton had achieved in the understanding of nature.   If such an ambition could have been achieved, it would have produced a unified "science of man".
    What actually happened in the following century was that many such disciplines appeared, which, so far from being unified, adopted many different and sometimes conflicting assumptions and approaches.  One view of this is that diversity is good, and that we do not need to worry about apparent conflicts.  In the search for knowledge and understanding, "let a hundred flowers bloom".  Another view is that such diversity of knowledge is superficial: in the end, it should be able to be reduced to our knowledge of the basic material realities of the world.  Another view again is that we should try to find how the human sciences are articulated: how they are related, which ones depend on which other ones, and in what way.

go to summary

Grand Theories

    One response to these options was the formulation of "grand theories:".  History is, of course, littered with obsolete or forgotten "-isms", "-ics" and "-ologies".  And new ones are being created all the time.  Some are short-lived, others rather stable and long-lasting.  Often they claim for themselves the status of "separate disciplines".
    There can be intellectual reasons for this reflected in the way in which we bootstrap ourselves from our common-sense ways of perceiving and understanding the world into the creation of the sciences.  This is seen, for instance, in the extraordinarily wide-ranging work of Aristotle, who created, four centuries before the common era, many of the disciplines which we recognize today, and viewed each of them as having a distinct subject-matter and purpose and method (e.g. economics, ethics, psychology, logic, political theory, rhetoric, zoology, anatomy, botany, physics, astronomy, linguistics, legal theory, chemistry, mathematics).  [See the work of Scott Atran.]
    But there can also be psychological and social reasons to claim disciplinary distinctness: it creates networks of solidarity; it can make it easier to obtain resources (salaries, research grants, etc.), and to obtain the ear of those in power.  At the individual level, it can be satisfying and advantageous to belong to or to be a leading or founding figure in such a group.
    Some grand theories, such as Functionalism in sociology, claim the autonomy of the social.  Some, such as methodological individualism, claim the priority of the psychological.  Some, such as sociobiology, claim the priority of the biological.  Some, such as Marxism, claim the priority of the economic base.
    Such grand theories have led to interesting work and insights, and the clashes between them have also often been fruitful.  But it is safer to be suspicious of Grand Theories.  The grander they are, the more dangerous they may be.  These dangers are not only intellectual, but sometimes practical.  (Consider, for instance, racist theories).


go to summary


go to summary


go to summary


go to summary

The Articulation of the Sciences

    A different view from autonomy/reduction is that we should consider how the sciences are articulated.  The underlying analogy here is the "articulation" of bones in a skeleton.  The OED defines "articulation" as "the structure or mechanism whereby two bones, or two parts of the invertebrate skeleton, are connected, whether stiffly, or in such a way that one moves in or on the other."  So we have questions like how do different sciences fit together, support each other, operate in connection with or move relative to each other ... 


go to summary

Sociobiology: an inflated model

    Sociobiology attempts to provide an account of human cultures and dispositions by the direct application of evolutionary theory.  It attempts to explain why certain kinds of behaviour occur by saying that they have a selective advantage for the members of the species in which they occur.  A great deal of work has been done on this which varies from the excellent to the atrocious.
    It can be inflated when it tries to deal with too much too globally.  The philosopher Thomas Hobbes in the seventeenth century took the view that human beings were basically aggressive, and we must understand and explain the existence and the form of civil society in light of this fact.  But is it a fact?  How could we set about showing that it is true ?  Some popular sociobiologists make up evolutionary stories about the importance to early humans of aggressiveness.  The trouble is that these stories are too speculative.  More important, we should notice that the scope of instinct in human behaviour is limited (even if important).  Most complex forms of human behaviour, even where they have an instinctual base, are learned and many are improvised.  This means that "no culture is hard-wired into any human being".  How then is it transmitted, and could evolutionary explanations nevertheless apply to it ?

Here is some relevant reading:
 

See the material put up by Francis Steen at
http://humanitas.ucsb.edu/users/steen/CogWeb/EP.html, especially
http://humanitas.ucsb.edu/users/steen/CogWeb/Sociobiology.html.

There is also a large bibliography on the evolution of cooperation by Robert Axelrod at
http://www.ipps.lsa.umich.edu/ipps/papers/coop/Evol_of_Coop_Bibliography.txt.


go to summary

The Epidemiology of Culture: a non-grand model
     For an alternative approach, suggested by Dan Sperber, see http://www.hku.hk/philodep/tm/sperber.htm.
FCTM
27 November 1997

GO BACK TO COURSE OUTLINE