Mozi (Mo Tzu or Micius)

Mo Tzu (herafter Mozi, ca. 490-403 BC) was China’s first true philosopher. Mozi pioneered the argumentative essay style, constructed the first normative and political theories. He formulated a pragmatic theory of language that gave classical Chinese philosophy its distinctive Character. Speculations about Mozi's origins highlight the social mobility of the era. The "Warring States" demand for scholars perhaps drew him from the lower ranks of craftsmen. Some stories picture him as a military fortifications expert. His criticisms show that he was intimately familiar with Confucianism.

Mohism became highly influential as technical intelligence challenged traditional priestcraft. Mencius (MENCIUS 371-289 BC) complained that the "words of Mozi and Yang Zhu fill the social world." The Mohist movement eventually spawned a school of philosophy of language (The Later Mohists) that shaped the mature philosophies of both Daoism (CHUANG TZU or ZHUANGZI ca 360 BC) and Confucianism (HSUN TZU or XUNZI 298-238 BC).

The core Mohist texts have a deliberate argumentative style. It uses balanced symmetry of expression and repetition that suggests it was intended for easy memorization and popular effect. These are a natural stylistic aid, signaling grammatical and logical structure, for an analytic language like Classical Chinese which lacked part-of-speech inflections. The style suggests deliberate authorship, but the reference to "The Master Mozi" confirms that students probably transcribed polished orations into the artificial literary written form.

The craft explanation of the Mohist movement helps us understand the distinctive character of disciplined philosophical thought in China. In Mohist analysis the issue is which standards guide the execution of instructions. Mozi's moral and linguistic reasoning and examples routinely appeal to measurement-like operations. His grounds are best understood as an appeal to reliable standards for fixing the reference of moral terms. Rather than a search for the ultimate moral axiom, Mozi searches for a constant standard of moral interpretation.

Mozi's attack on commonsense traditionalism illustrates how it is inconstant. Mozi tells a story of a tribe that kills and eats their first born sons. We cannot, he observes, accept that this tradition is yimoral or renbenevolent. This shows the error of treating tradition as a standard for the application of such terms. So, he argues, we need some more reliable standard for applying these terms and thus declaring which traditions are moral and should be made constant.

Mozi's search for a reliable standard links his Utilitarianism to his focus on tiannature:sky. Tian was the traditional source of political authority ("the mandate of heaven") that was "naturalized" in the philosophical period. It was characterized by the changconstancy. Mozi exploited its connotation of authority to argue for a non-traditional standard of ethical choice. We can flee from a family, a society, even a kingdom, if we do not like its way. We cannot similarly escape the constancies of nature.

Conveniently, the constant natural urge he identified was one that he also thought could be reliably measured—the distinction between benefit and harm. Thus he proposed using that as the "uncontroversial" or universal standard to determine which traditional practices count as 'moral' and 'benevolent'. The will of tian, he says, is like a compass or a square. It does not depend on a cultivated intuition or indoctrination.

The moral reform of society takes place by reforming the social daoguiding discourse. The discourse that society uses to educate people is internalized and becomes their devirtuosity, their disposition to moral behavior. Devirtuosity produces a course of action in real time. Whether the course produced by discourse like "When X do Y" is successful or not depends on what actors identify as "X" and "not-X." For the sake of social coordination, we train humans to make these distinctions in similar ways. The key way to reform guiding discourse is to reform how we make distinctions, e.g. the distinction between 'moral' and 'immoral'.

Mozi understands the training process in several related ways. (1) we emphasize or make a different set of distinctions the dominant ones--hence provide different words for programming dispositions. For example, he says the ruler should use the word jianuniversal and not the word biepartial. We make the benefit-promoting names constant in our social discourse. (2) We reform how we make the distinctions associated with terms which remain the same. For example, we will assign different things to shiright and feiwrong. (3) We can change the order of terms in the guiding discourse--use it to give different advice.

Notice that Mozi's posture as a moral reformer puts him in an argumentative bind that is related to one faced by Utilitarianism in the West. He admits he is challenging existing judgments and intuitions. What is the status of the principle he uses in proposing his alternative? How can he make his alternative seems other than immoral to someone from within that tradition? How can a moral reformer get over the impasse posed by conflicting moral intuitions?

One possibility emerges in another of Mozi's philosophical stories. He uses the story to criticize Confucian pro-family and "partial" moral attitudes. His story depicts a conscript leaving his family to make war. It argues that if he were concerned about his family, he would want those to whom he entrusts them to adopt an attitude of more universal concern. He would, Mozi argues, not seek out a person with "partial" moral attitudes. The family centered moral attitude is "inconstant" in the sense that it leads him to prefer that shared social attitudes be more universal than his own. He would achieve his "partial" goals only if the public morality were altruistic. Confucian partiality is "inconstant" in that it chooses its own rejection as a public daoguiding discourse.

Mozi's analysis shows Chinese thought has a notion of morality as independent from social conventions and history. However, it does not tie morality to the familiar Western concept of "reason" nor of principles or maxims which function within a belief-desire psychology. The psychological and conceptual structure of Mozi's moral analysis treats human nature as social and malleable. Human malleability derives from our tendency to learn, to mimic, to seek support and approval from those we respect—our social superiors. It derives also from the effect of language on "inner programming."

Mozi promotes renhumanity as the appropriate utilitarian disposition—the virtue of benevolence. He links it to his choice of universal over partial "love." Mozi acknowledges that instilling universal moral concern requires social reinforcement--official promotion and encouragement. The system that brings this about is Mozi's social theory of shang-tongagreeing with the superior. Here Mozi gives a familiar "hypothetical choice" justification of a system of authority.

Mozi's theory asks why we would choose ordered society over anarchy—the original state of nature. His description is of a state of inefficiency and waste. Mozi sees humans as naturally moral creatures who disagree. Prior to society, humans had different yimorality. They end up in conflicts fueled by moral judgments. They cannot agree on what is shiright and feiwrong. It is clear, he says, that the bad situation arises from the absence of a zhangelder. So [we] select a worthy man and name him tian-zinatural master. He then selects others of worth and creates the governing hierarchy. It works by harmonizing our yimorality, our use of shithis:right and feinot-this:wrong. We report "up" what we see as shithis:right and feinot-this:wrong; the superior endorses it and then we all call shi what he calls shi.

Note the absence of any concept of law or retributive punishment. People are punished in Mozi's political world for failing to join in the utility preserving system of coordinating our attitudes, but not for violations of rules promulgated by the superior. All the superior "promulgates" is moral judgments. What society gains is coordination of behavior through a "constant" daoguiding discourse. Making the judgment that something is shiright amounts to choosing it.

The ruler does not have arbitrary discretion in his assignments of shi-feiright-wrong and all humans have access to the natural measurement standard. Ultimately we "conform upward" only when we correctly use the utility standard in judgment. Still, agreement is itself a utilitarian good, so we report our judgments up, and accept the unified judgment that comes down.

This tension among standards for language use becomes explicit in Mozi's account of three fameasurement standards for yanlanguage. He lists first the model of past sage kings. Second, he observes the importance of standards to which ordinary people have access "through their eyes and ears." Clear, measurement-like standards can be applied by "even the unskillful" with good results. He lists the pragmatic appeal to usefulness third. While it anchors his reform spirit, he clearly recognizes the importance of historical and traditional patterns in determining correct usage.

Mozi applies his standards in a famous set of arguments concerning 'spirits' and 'fate'. He appeals to what the sage kings and old literature say, what people in general say, using their "eyes and ears" and, most importantly, what effects on behavior will result from saying "have spirits" vs. "lack spirits" or "have fate" vs. "lack fate." Mozi acknowledges that there may be no spirits. Still, he argues, the standards of language all weigh in favor of saying 'have'. He characterizes his conclusion as knowing the daoway of 'have-lack'. Knowing how to deploy this distinction is knowing to say 'have' of spirits and 'lack' of fate. We change the content of discourse via making the have-lack distinction in a particular way.

Mohism died out when the emerging imperial dynastic system promoted a Confucian orthodoxy. Mozi's long term influence is controversial. Confucian histories treat Mohism as a brief, inconsequential interlude of "Western Style thought." However, his influence arguably shaped Confucian orthodoxy as much as did Confucius. Mozi made classical Confucians defend their normative theory philosophically and in doing so, they adopted his terms of analysis and his key ethical attitudes. Paradoxically, the vehicle for the absorption of Mohist ideas was his chief detractor, Mencius who effectively abandons traditionalism and constructs a Confucian version of benevolence-based naturalism.

Daoism, similarly, grew out of their relativistic analysis of the Confucian-Mohist debate. Arguably, we owe to Mozi the fact that Chinese philosophy exists. Without him, Confucianism might never have risen above "wise man" sayings and Daoism might have languished as nothing more than a "Yellow Emperor" cult.

 

Bibliography

 

Graham, Angus. 1978 Later Mohist Logic, Ethics and Science (Hong Kong and London: Chinese University Press) .

Hansen, Chad. 1989 "Mozi: Language Utilitarianism: The Structure of Ethics in Classical China," The Journal of Chinese Philosophy 16 pp. 355-380.

Hansen, Chad. 1992 A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought (New York: Oxford University Press)

Mei, Y. P.. 1929 The Ethical and Political Works of Mo-tse (London: Arthur Probsthain) .

Mei, Y. P.. 1934 Mo-tse, the Neglected Rival of Confucius (London: Arthur Probsthain) .