Bohm, David, Causality and Chance in Modern Physics,
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1957, pp. 20-23/55-7

Summary

8.  CONTINGENCY, CHANCE, AND STATISTICAL LAW


 Now contingencies are, as we have pointed out in Section 1, possibilities existing outside the context under discussion.  The essential characteristic of contingencies is that their nature cannot be defined or inferred solely in terms of the properties of things within the context in question.  In other words, they have a certain relative independence of what is inside this context.  However, as we have seen, our general experience shows that all things are interconnected in some way and to some degree.  Hence we never expect to find complete independence.  But to the extent that the interconnection is negligible, we may abstract out from the real process and its interconnections the notion of chance contingencies, which are idealized, as completely independent of the context under discussion.  Thus, like the notion of necessary causal connections, the notion of chance contingencies is seen to be an approximation, which gives a partial treatment of certain aspects of the real process, but which eventually has to be corrected and completed by a consideration of the causal interconnections that always exist between the processes taking place in different contexts.  In order to bring out in more detail what is meant by chance, we may consider a typical chance event; namely, an automobile accident.   Now it is evident that just where, when, and how a particular accident takes place depends on an enormous number of factors, a slight change of any one of which could greatly change the character of the accident or even avoid it altogether.  For example, in a collision of two cars, if one of the motorists had started out ten seconds earlier or ten seconds later, or if he had stopped to buy cigarettes, or slowed down to avoid a cat that happened to cross the road, or for any one of an unlimited number of similar reasons, this particular accident would not even have happened; while even a slightly different turn of the steering wheel might either have.prevented the accident altogether or might have changed its character completely, either for the better or for the worse.  We see, then, that relative to a context in which we consider,for example, the actions and precautions that can be taken by a particular motorist, each accident has an aspect that is fortuitous.  By this we mean that what happens is contingent on what are, to a high degree of approximation, independent factors, existing outside the context in question, which have no essential relationship to the characteristic traits that define just what sort of a person this motorist is and how he will behave in a given situation.  For this reason, we say that relative to such a context a particular collision is not a necessary or inevitable development, but rather that it is an accident and comes about by chance, from which it also follows that within this context, the question of just where, when, and how such a collision will take place, as well as that of whether it will take place or not, is unpredictable. 
 go back to summary 

 So much for an individual accident.  Let us now consider a series of similar accidents.  First of all, we note that there is an irregular and unpredictable variation or fluctuation in the precise details of the various accidents (e. g. precisely when and where they take place, precisely what is destroyed, etc.).  The origin of this variation is easily understood since a great many of the independent factors on which the details of the accidents depend fluctuate in a way having no systematic relationship to what a particular motorist may be doing.
    As the number of accidents under consideration becomes larger and larger, however, new properties begin to appear; for one finds that individual variations tend to cancel out, and statistical regularities begin to show themselves.  Thus, the total number of accidents in a particular region generally does not change very much from ear to year, and the changes that do take place often show a regular trend.  Moreover, this trend can be altered in a systematic way by the alteration of specified factors on which accidents depend.  Thus, when laws are passed punishing careless driving and requiring regular inspection of mechanicalparts, tyres, etc., the mean rate of accidents in any given region has been almost always found to undergo a definite trend downward.  In the case of an individual motorist taking a particular trip, no very definite predictions can in general be made concerning the effects of such measures, since there are still an enormous number of sources of accidents that have not yet been eliminated; yet statistically, as we have seen, variations in a particular cause produce a regular and predictable trend in the effect.

 go back to summary 

 The behaviour described above is found in a very wide range of fields, including social, economic, medical, and scientific statistics and many other applications.  In all these fields, there is a characteristic irregular fluctuation or variation in the behaviour of individual objects, events, and phenomena, the details of which are not predictable within the context under discussion.  This is combined with regular trends in the behaviour of a long series or large aggregate of such objects, events, or phenomena.  These regular trends lead to what we maycall statistical laws, which permit the approximate prediction of the properties of the "long run" or average behaviour of a long series or large aggregate ofindividuals, without the need to go to a broader context in which we would take into account additional causal factors that contribute to governing the details of the fluctuations of the individual members of such series of aggregates.

 go back to summary 

 The tendency for contingencies lying outside a given context to fluctuate approximately independently of happenings inside that context has demonstrated itself to be so widespread that one may enunciate it as a principle; namely, the principle of randomness.  By randomness we mean just that this independence leads to fluctuation of these contingencies in a very complicated way over a wide range of possibilities, but in such a manner that statistical averages have aregular and approximately predictable behaviour.

 go back to summary 

 It is clear, then, that when we know that a certain fluctuation is due to chance contingencies lying outside the context of the causal laws under discussion, we know more than the mere fact that the causal laws in question do not give perfectly accurate predictions; we know also that the contingencies will produce complicated fluctuations having regular statistical trends.  Consider, for example, the problem of error in measurement discussed in the previous section.  Such errors are generally divided into two classes, systematic and random.  Systematic errors arise, but they are just due to external causes, and not to real chance contingencies that fluctuate independently of the context in question.  To reduce systematic errors, we must obtain an improved understanding and control of the factors that are responsible for the error.  The random part of the error can, however, be reduced simply by taking the average of more and more measurements.  For, according to a well-known theorem, the effects of chance fluctuations tend to cancel out in such a way that this part of the error is inversely proportional to the square root of the number of measurements.  This shows how the fact that a certain effect comes from chance contingencies implies more than the fact that the causes lie outside the context under discussion.  It implies, in addition, a certain objective characteristic of randomness in the factors in which the effect originates.  We see, then, that it is appropriate to speak about objectively valid laws of chance, which tell us about a side of nature that is not treated completely by the causal laws alone.  Indeed, the laws of chance are just as necessary as the causal laws themselves.  For example, the random character of chance fluctuations is, in a wide variety of situations, made inevitable by the extremely complex and manifold character of the external contingencies on which the fluctuations depend.  (Thus random errors in measurement arise, as we have seen, in a practically unlimited number of different kinds of factors that are essentially independent of the quantity that is being measured.)  Moreover, this random character of the fluctuations is quite often an inherent and indispensable part of the normal functioning of many kinds of things, and of their modes of being.  Thus, it would be impossible for a modern city to continue to exist in its normal condition unless there were a tendency towards the cancellation of chance fluctuations in traffic, in the demand for various kinds of food,clothing, etc., in the times at which various individuals get sick or die, etc.  In all kinds of fields we find a similar dependence on the characteristic effects of chance.  Thus, when sand and cement are mixed, one does not carefully distribute each individual grain of sand and cement so as to obtain a uniform mixture, but rather one stirs the sand and cement together and depends on chance to produce a uniform mixture....

 go back to summary 

 A systematic application of the theory of probability to atomic physics is carried out in the study of statistical mechanics, which makes possible fairly precise calculation of a great many macroscopic properties of the system (e.g. entropy, heat capacity, equation of state, etc.) on the basis of the microscopic laws, and which also provides a model permitting a quantitative treatment of the way in which the macroscopic laws of thermodynamics arise out of the microscopic motions.  It has also been applied in the study of Brownian motion, and in the study of the fluctuations of the macroscopic properties of matter near the criticalpoints of liquids. Thus, the theory of probability has made an important contribution to ourunderstanding of the relationship between microscopic and macroscopic levels by permitting us to take into account chance phenomena originating in the microscopic level without the need for either a precise and a detailed calculation of the motions of all the individual molecules in a large aggregate or a precise knowledge of the laws of the microscopic level.

 go back to summary 

.............................................................................
13.  THE ENRICHMENTS OF THE CONCEPTUAL STRUCTURE OF
CLASSICAL PHYSICS AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF MECHANISM

 We have seen in the preceding sections that, even apart from the development of the notion of fields, there occurred, during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries a number of very important additional steps that considerably enriched the conceptual structure of physics.  These included the introduction of the concept of levels, that of quantitative changes that lead to qualitative changes, and that of chance fluctuations that tend towards approximately determinate laws for the mean behaviour of large aggregates.  While, as we have already pointed out in Section 4, none of these concepts is in direct contradiction to a mechanistic philosophy, every one of them constitutes, in its general trend and spirit at least, a step away from the idea that there is an absolute and final fundamental law, which is purely quantitative in form, and which would by itself permit, in principle at least, the complete and perfect calculation of every feature of everything in the whole universe.


 go back to summary 

 To see why these new concepts tend to lead away from mechanism we first recall that in the original form of the mechanistic philosophy, both the notion of qualitative changes and that of chance were regarded as nothing more than subjective aids to our thinking about the properties of matter en masse, so that they did not represent anything that was actually supposed to exist objectively in material systems.  We have already seen in Section II, however, that at least within the macroscopic domain, in a qualitative transformation, new qualities satisfying new laws become the significant and dominant causes in the domain in question.  Moreover, the objective reality of the breaks in quantitative macroscopic properties, as well as that of the insensitivity of the qualitative change to quantitative details also cannot be denied.  Similarly, it is evident (on the basis of the discussions given in Chapter 1, Sections 8 and 9) that chance fluctuations exist objectively within specified contexts, and that the theory of probability provides a relatively precise mathematical expression of objective properties of these fluctuations, including the statistical regularities which arise (on the basis of the cancellation of large numbers of chance fluctuations).

 go back to summary 

    It is a most important characteristic of the mechanistic philosophy, however, that it permits one to make a limitless number of adjustments in his detailed point of view, without giving up what is essential to the mechanistic position.  Thus, with the notion of qualitative changes, a great many physicists have effectively accepted the idea that these may well be objective (or at least as objective as anything else is).  Nevertheless, they assert that such changes are not of fundamental significance, because they must, in principle at least, follow completely and perfectly in all of their details, in every respect, and without any approximation, from the quantitative laws of motion of the fundamental elements that make up the system, whatever these elements may be.  Hence, it is maintained that qualitative changes are like passing shadows that have absolutely no independent existence of their own, but which depend for all their attributes on the quantitative laws governing the basic elements entering into the theory.  It is evident that such an attitude implies also that the notion of a series of levels of law is likewise nothing more than a set of approximations to the absolute and final fundamental law, approximations in which the laws of the various levels depend completely for all their characteristics on the fundamental law, while the fundamental law has no dependence whatever on the laws of the various levels. Similarly, it is consistent with this point of view to suppose that chance and statistical laws arise out of nothing more than the sheer complexity and multiplicity of the motions of the basic entities entering into the fundamental causal law and that into the formulation of this latter law no element of chance whatever will appear.

 go back to summary 
    We recall that historically the mechanistic philosophy was expressed in terms of the assumption that the basic units out of which the universe was supposed to be built are indivisible atoms.  The purely quantitative laws governing the motions of these atoms, were then regarded as the laws from which everything else followed.  It was discovered later,however, that the atoms are not really the fundamental units, because ... [and so the story goes on ...]

GO BACK TO THE MAIN PAGE ON CHANCE