Topic RS: Completeness and Soundness


1 Why the rules are good, part 1

In Topic DS you learned how to make derivations
in our natural deduction system; you learned how
to use the rules to show that a formula is derivable
from other formulas. But now in Topic 2 let us reflect
on the strengths and weaknesses of this rule system.
In this topic, instead of working
within the system,
you will study
about the system.
This sort of study is called
metalogic or metatheory, and
is an important part of the study of logic. For any tool, one
should learn not only how to use the tool, but one should
learn about the tool-- what the tool can and cannot do.

Here are some questions one might ask:
Why are these rules good rules?
Are some other rules better?
What happens if we change the rules?
Should we change the rules?


1.1 Two sound rules

One reason that the rules are good is that
the rules ensure that each formula you write
down is
entailed by its dependencies.
That is, for each line of a derivation, if the
dependencies are true, then the formula is true.

Consider this short derivation:

derivation

If the dependency of line 1 is true, then the
formula on line 1 is true. Line 1 is "(A&B)".
The dependency of line 1 is line 1, which is "(A&B)".
And if "(A&B)" is true then "(A&B)" must be true:

(A&B)
models (A&B)

In other words, "(A&B)" entails "(A&B)".
(Note that the symbol "
models" is the double turnstile
which you learned about in
SL05.5, not the single
turnstile "
proves" discussed in Topic DS01.)

If the dependency of line 2 is true, then the
formula on line 2 is true. Line 2 is "A".
The dependency of line 2 is line 1, which is "(A&B)".
And, if "(A&B)" is true then "A" must be true:

(A&B)
models A

In other words, "(A&B)" entails "A".
You can see that from a truth table:

truthtable


This truth table shows that in every case where
"(A&B)" is true, "A" is true too.

In a certain sense, you won't go wrong when
you use Rule A or Rule &E. Rule A and Rule &E are
both
sound rules: when following these rules, the
formula you write down is entailed by its dependencies.

Exercise 1.1a
Explain why &I,
I and E are all sound rules.

1.2 The soundness of the system

If you think about each of the rules in our natural
deduction system, you will see that each of the 12
rules is sound. (We won't discuss each of the rules here,
but you can verify yourself that each is sound.)
So at every line in every derivation,
the formula on that line is entailed by its dependencies.

Our system, therefore, has the property of
soundness: if a formula is derivable in the system
from some formulas, it is entailed by the formulas.

More precisely, soundness means that:

For any formula
φ, if proves φ, then models φ,

and


For any formula
φ, and list of formulas X,
if
X proves φ then X models φ.

Exercise 1.2a

Would the system be sound if we add the following rule?

If you have derived (φφ), you can write down φ,
depending on everything (φ
φ) depends on.

Exercise 1.2b

Would the system be sound if we remove rule &I?

Exercise 1.2c

Would the system be sound if we change rule
I this way?
Why or why not?


If you have derived φ, and you have derived ψ,
you can write down (φ
ψ),
depending on everything ψ depends on except φ.


1.3 Why sound rules are good

At this point one might wonder why it is good to have
a system that is sound. One way to think about that
would be to suppose an unsound rule is
added to the system:

Flip rule
If you have derived φ, you can write down ~φ,
depending on everything φ depends on.


Then one could make the following derivation:

derivation


Thus, C is derivable from B. And, by changing "B"
to any formula
φ and "C" to any formula ψ, one
can show that
φ is derivable from ψ. In the revised
system, anything is derivable from anything!

The revised system is useless, insofar as one
hopes to use a deduction system to show when
a conclusion follows from some premises in
an argument. For a conclusion of an argument
does not always follow from the premises.

Exercise 1.3a

Suppose we add the flip rule and remove
Rule
E from our natural deduction system.
Would the resulting system be sound?



1.4 Derivations and truth tables

One way to find out whether a sequent
is valid is to make a truth table. For example,
a truth table will show whether or not this is
a valid sequent:

((P Q)→ R) models (P → R)

In the truth table, if there is a line where
"
((P Q)→ R)" is true and "(P → R)" is false,
then the sequent is invalid. Otherwise the
sequent is valid.

Since our natural deduction system is sound,
you can use it to show that a sequent is valid.
You can make a derivation to show the right hand
side of the sequent is derivable from the left hand side:

((P Q)→ R) proves (P → R)

and, then, since our system is sound, it follows that
the sequent is valid.

((P Q)→ R) models (P → R).